The reflective practitioner
Noter
Download noter i PDF-format
Af: Birgitte Michelsen
Schöns ærinde: At tilbyde
et alternativ til den traditionelle praksis-epistemologi. Alternativet
kalder han reflection-in-action-
Forord
I begin with
the assumption that competent practitioners usually know more than
they can say. They exhibit a kind of knowing in practice, most of
which is tacit…Indeed practitioners themselves often reveal
a capacity for reflection on their intuitive knowing in the midst
of action and sometimes use this capacity to cope with the unique,
uncertain, and conflicted situations of practice . (8-9)
Part one:
Professional knowledge and reflection in action
But the questioning
of professionals rights and freedoms – their license to determine
who shall be allowed to practice, their mandate for social control,
their autonomy – has been rooted in a deeper questioning of
the professionals´ claim to extraordinary knowledge in matters of
human importance. (5)
The crisis
of confidence in the professions, and perhaps also the decline in
professional self-image, seems to be rooted in a growing skepticism
about professional effectiveness in the larger sense, a skeptical
reassessment of the professionals actual contribution to society´s
well-being through the delivery of competent services based on special
knowledge. (13)
Problems are
interconnected, envitoments are turbulent, and the future is indeterminate
just in so far as managers can shape it by their actions. What is
called for, under these conditions, is not only the analytic techniques
which have been traditional in operations research, but the active,
synthetic skill of ”designing a desirable future and inventing
ways of bringing it about.” (16, citat fra Russell
Ackoff, 1979)
The unique
case calls for an art of practice which ”might be taught,
if it were constant and known, but it is not constant.” (16-17
– citat a Harvey Brooks)
Practitioners
are frequently embroiled in conflicts of values, goals, purposes
and interests. (17)
Competing views
of professional practice – competing images of the professional
role, the central values of the profession, the relevant knowledge
and skills – have come into good currency. (17)
As Edgar Schein
has put it, there are three components to professional knowlegde:
An underlying
discipline or basic science component upon which the practice rests
or from which it is developed.
An applied
science or ”engineering” component from which many of
the day-to-day diagnostic procedures and problem-solutions are derived.
A skills and
attitudinal component that concerns the actual performance of services
to the client, using the underlying basic and applied knowledge.
(24, Schein: Professional Education, 1973)
The researchers
role is distinct from, and usually considered superior to, the role
of the practitioner. (26)
(30 ff om hvordan positivismen
og den tekniske rationalitet har affødt ekspert-vældet)
From the perspective
of Technical Rationality, professional practice is a process of
problem solving. Problems of choice or decision are solved through
the selection, from available means, of the one best suited to establish
ends. But with this emphasis on problem solving, we ignore problem
setting, the process by which we define the decision to be made,
the ends to be achieved, the means which may be chosen. In real-world
practice, problems do not present themselves to the practitioner
as givens. They must be constructed from the materials of problem
situations which are puzzling, troubling, and uncertain. (40)
Problem setting
is a process in which, interactively, we name the things to which
we will attend and frame the context in which we will attend to
them. (40)
Let us search,
instead, for an epistemology of practice implicit in the artistic,
intuitive processes which some practitioners do bring to situations
of uncertainty, instability, uniqueness, and value conflict. (49)
Knowing in
action: Knowing has the following properties:
There are actions,
recognitions, and judgements which we know how to carry out spontaneously;
we do not have to think about them prior to or during their performance.
We are often
unaware of having learned to do these things; we simply find ourselves
doing them.
In some cases,
we were once aware of the understandings which were subsequently
internalized in our feeling for the stuff of action. In other cases,
we may never have been aware of them. In both cases, however, we
are usually unable to describe the knowing which our action reveals.
(54)
Reflecting
in action: Improvisation consists on varying, combining and recombining
a set of figures within the schema which bounds and gives coherence
to the performance. (55)
They (musikere)
are reflecting in action on the music they are collectively making
and on their individual contributions to it, thinking what they
are doing and, in the process, evolving their way of doing it. (56)
A practitioners reflection can
serve as s corrective to overlearning. Through reflection, he can
surface and criticize the tacit understandings that have grown up
around the repepitive experiences of a specialized practice, and
can make new sense of the situations of uncertainty or uniqueness
which he may allow himself to practice. (61)
When a practitioner
reflects in and on his practice, the possible objects of his reflection
are as varied as the kinds of phenomena before him and the systems
of knowing-in-practice which he brings to them. He may reflect on
the tacit norms and appreciations which underlies a judgement, or
on the strategies and theories implicit a pattern of behaviour.
He may reflect on the feeling for a situation which has led him
to adopt a particular course of action, on the way in which he has
framed the problem he is trying to solve, or on the role he has
constructed for himself within a larger institutional context. (62)
…then
the practitioner may surface and criticize his initial understanding
of the phenomenon, construct a new description of it, and test the
new description by an on-the-spot experiment. Sometimes he arrives
at a new theory of the phenomenon by articulating a feelimg he has
about it. (dvs. at reframe problemet jf. Christrup. Jeg synes
at Schön beskriver dette temmelig opskrift-agtigt!) (63)
The practitioner
allows himself to experience surprise, puzzlement, or confusion
in a situation which he finds uncertain or unique. He reflects on
the phenomena before him, and on the prior understandings which
have been implicit in his behaviour. He carries out an experiment
which serves to generate both a new understanding of the phenomena
and the change in the situation.
When someone
reflects in action, he becomes a researcher in the practice context.
He is not dependent on the categories of established theory and
technique, but constructs a new theory of the unique case. (68)
Part two:
Professional context for reflection in action
Architects:
In a good process of design, this conversation with the situation
is reflective. In answer to the situations back-talk, the designer
reflects in action on the construction of the problem, the strategies
of action, or the model of the phenomena, which have been implicit
in his moves. (79)
Eksempel med en arkitektstuderende
Petra der vejledes af sin lærer Quist s. 79ff.
Petras problem
solving has led her to a dead end. Quist reflects critically on
the main problem she has set, reframes it, and proceeds to work
out the consequences of the new geometry he has imposed on the screwy
site. (102)
Psychotherapy: The supervision
session, samtale mellem en psykoterapeut Resident og dennes supervisor
S, som søger efter mønstre og opridser alternativer, s. 109 ff.
Having constructed
and tested a solution to the puzzle, the Supervisor means to keep
it open to further inquiry. The Resident should use the tentative
solution to guide his work with the patient, but he should keep
the puzzle alive. (124)
The structure
of reflection in action:
Because each
practitioner treats his case as unique, he cannot deal with it in
applying standard teories or techniques. In the half hour or so
that he spends with the student, he must construct an understanding
of the situation as he finds it. And because he finds the situation
problematic, he must reframe it. (129)
But the practitioners
moves also produce unintended changes which give the situation new
meanings. The situation talks back, the practitioner listens, and
as he appreciates what he hears, he reframes the situation once
again. (131-132)
When the practitioner
tries to solve the problem he has set, he seeks both to understand
the situation and to change it. (134)
The practitioner
has built up a repertoire of exambles, images, understandings, and
actions… When a practitioner makes sense of a situation he
percieves to be unique, he sees it as something already present
in his repertoire.(138)
Seeing-as is
not enough, however. When a practitioner sees a new situation as
some element of his repertoire, he gets a new way of seeing it and
a new possibility for action in it, but the adequacy and utility
of his new view must still be discovered in action. Reflection in
action necessarily involves experiment. (141)
Exploratory
experiment is the probing, playful activity by which we get a feel
for things. It succeeds when it leads to the discovery of something
there. (145)
Movetesting
experiments: We take action in order to produce an intended change.
(146)
Hypothesis
testing experiments succeeds when it effects as intended discrimination
among competing hypotheses. (146)
When the practitioner
reflects in action in a case he percieves as unique, paying attention
to phenomena and surfacing his intuitive understanding of them,
his experimenting is at once exploratory, move testing and hypothesis
testing. The three functions are fulfilled by the very same actions.
(147)
The situations
of Quist and the Supervisor are, in important ways, not the real
thing. ..Each is operating in a virtual world, a constructed representation
of the real world of practice. This fact is significant for the
question of rigor in experimenting. In his virtual world, the practitioner
can manage some of the constrains to hypothesis-testing experiment
which are inherent in the world of his practice. (157)
Drawing functions
as a context for experiment precisely because it enables the designer
to eliminate features of the real world situation which might confound
or disrupt his experiments, but when he comes to interpret the results
of his experiments, he must remember tha factors that have been
elinimated. (159)
Storytelling represents and
substitutes for firsthand experience….Once a story has been
told, it can be held as datum, considered at leisure for its meanings
and its relationsships with other stories. …By attending
to a few features which he considers central, the Supervisor can
isolate the main thread of a story from the surrounding factors
which he chooses to consider as noise. (160)
In improvisation,
musical or dramatic, participants can conducts on the spot experiments
in which, as improvisation tends towards performance, the boundaries
between virtual and real worlds may become blurred. (162)
Reflective
practice in the sciencebased professions: Eksempel med ingeniørstuderende,
der afprøver alternative metoder s. 171ff.
At each stage
of this process the students were contronted with puzzles and problems
that did not fit their known categories, yet they had a sense of
the kinds of theories that might explain these phenomena. They used
their theoretical hunches to guide experiment, but on several occasions
their moves led to puzzling outcomes – a process that worked,
a stubborn defect – on which they then reflected. Each such
reflection gave rise to new experiments and to new phenomena, troublesome
or desirable, which led to further reflection and experiment. (176)
(åbenhed således vigtig for denne spiralprocess, og at turde gå
videre end blot reproducere det kendte)
In the examples
just described, there was a crucially important step, one often
attributed to ”creaticity” or ”intuition”….Faced
with unexpected and puzzling phenomena, the inquirers made initial
descriptions which guided their further investigation. …They
(beskrivelserne) are, at least on some occasions, outcomes of reflections
on a perceived similarity, a process which in the previous chapter
I called seeing-as. (182)
Thomas Kuhn
calls such process ”thinking from exemplars”. Once a
new problem is seen to be analogous to a problem previously solved,
then ”both an appropriate formalism and a new way of attaching
its symbolic consequenses naturally follow”. (Kuhn, Second
Thoughts) (183)
When the two
things seen as similar are initially very different from one another,
falling into what is usually considered different domains of experience,
then seeing-as takes a form I call ”generative metaphor”.
(183-184)
The idea of
reflection on seeing-as suggests a direction of inquiry into processes
which tend otherwise to be wystified and dismissed with the terms
”intuition” or ”creativity”, and it suggests
how these processes might be placed within the framework of reflective
conversation with the situation which I have proposed as a partial
account of the arts of engineering design and scientific investigation.
(187)
Town Planning:
Limits to reflection in action s. 204 ff
In some cases,
special interest groups took positions which were in direct and
explicit conflict with one another. In other cases, conflicts of
interest became clear only as the success of one movement led to
consequences contrary to the interests of another. In still other
cases, conflict became evident as the different movements found
themselves competing in hard times for scarce ressources. (207)
A professional
role places skeletal demands on a practitioners behaviour, but within
theses constraints, each individual develops his own way of framing
his role. Whether he chooses to his role frame from the professions
repertoire, or fashions it for himself, his professional knowlegde
takes on the character of a system. The problems he sets, the strategies
he employs, the facts the treats as relevant, and his interpersonal
theories of action are bound up with his way of framing his role.
(210) (Christrups term Socialt snask, eller Bourdieus relationer/magtstrukturer
er relevant her. Jf. Illeriis er der altså også både individuel
motivation og sociale relationer på spil når der skal ”reframes”,
ikke de kognitive processer alene)
Eksempel med en 'planner' der
diskuterer med en 'developer' og en arkitekt, s. 211ff
The planners
interpersonal theory of actions conforms to a model that Chris Argyris
and I have called Model 1. An individual who conforms to Model 1
behaves according to characteristic values and strategies of action.
(226)
The planner
in our protocol frames the problems of his meeting with the developer
in a Model 1 way and brings a Model 1 theory of action to their
solution. He percieves the review game, which he plays with the
developer, as a win/lose game. He sets and tries to solve the problems
by a strategy of mystery and mastery. (227)
Thus his framing
of the role, his setting of the problems of the meeting, and his
model 1 theory of action, make up a self-reinforcing system. One
could either say that he has framed role and problems to suit his
theory of action, or that he has evolved a theory of action suited
to the role and problems he has framed. (228)
An individuel
who conforms to Model 2 tries to satisfy the following values:
· Give and get valid information
· Seek out and provide others with directly observable data and correct
reports, so that valid attributions can be made.
· Create the conditions for free and informed choice.
· Try to create, for oneself and for others, awareness of the values
at stake in decision, awareness of the limits of one´s capacities,
and awareness of the zones of experience free of defense machanisms
beyond one´s control.
· Increase the likelihood of internal commitment to decisions made.
· Try to create conditions, for oneself and for others, in which the
individual is committed to an action because it is intrinsically
satisfying – not, as in the case of model 1, because it is
accompanied by external rewards or punishments. (231)
Among the strategies
for achieving these values, there are the following:
Make designing
and managing the enviroment a bilateral task, so that the several
parties to the situation can work toward freedom of choice and internal
commitment.
Make protection
of self or other a joint operation, so that one does not withold
negative information from the other without testing the attribution
that underlies the decision to withold.
Speak in directly
observable categories, providing the data from which one´s inference
are drawn and thereby opening then to disconfirmation.
Surface private dilemmas, so
as to encourage the public testing of the assumptions on which such
dilemmas depend. (231-232)
Role frame
is interdependent with interpersonal theory of action, and the resulting
system of knowing-in-practice has consequnces both for the practitioners
ability to detect crucial errors and for the scope and direction
of his reflection in action. (234-235)
The art of
managing: Reflection in action within an organizational learning
system s. 236ff
The field of
management has long been marked by a conflict between two competing
views of professional knowledge. On the first view, the manager
is a technician whose practice consists in applying to the everyday
problems of his organization the pinciples and methods derived from
management science. On the second, the manager is a craftsman, a
practitioner of the art of managing, that cannot be reduced to explicit
rules and theories. (236-237)
Managers have
become increasingly sensitive to the phenomena of uncertainty, change,
and uniqueness. In the last twnty years, ”decision and uncertainty”
has become a term of art. It has become commonplace for managers
to speak of the ”turbulent” enviroments in which problems
do not lend themselves to the techniques of benefit-cost analysis
or to probabilistic reasoning…Here they tend to speak not
of technique but of ”intuition”. (239)
In management as in other fields,
”art” has a two-fold meaning. It may mean intuitive
judgment and skill, the feeling for phenomena and for action
that I have called knowing-in-practice. But it may also designate
a manager´s reflection, in the context of action, on phenomena which
he percieves as incongruent with his intuitive understandings. (241)
A managers
life is wholly concerned with an organization which is both the
stage for his activity and the object of his inquiry. Hence, the
phenomena on which he reflects-in-action are the phenomena of organizational
life. (242)
Managers do
reflect-in-action, but they seldom reflect on their reflection-in-action…Since
he cannot describe his reflection-in-action, he cannot teach others
to do it. (243)
The interaction
between product development team and research laboratory can be
represented as a cycle of action and reaction. (259)
Credibility,
commitment, confidence and cempetence are interdependent. (261)
Considered
more broadly as an organizational learning system, the product development
game determines the directions and the limit of reflection-in-action.
When crisis present themselves, managers subject them to inquiry
– often with successful results – but they do not reflect
publicly on the processes which lead to such crises, for this would
surface the games of deception by which product development deals
with general management. While these games are ”open secrets”
within the organization, they are not publicly discussable. (263)
Patterns and
limits of reflection-in-action, s. 268ff
I have in mind
differences in the constants that various practitioners bring to
their reflection-in-action:
The media,
languages, and repertoires that practitioners use to describe reality
and conduct experiments.
The appreciative
systems they bring to problem setting, to the evaluation of inquiry,
and to reflective conversation.
The overarching
theories by which they make sense of phenomena.
The role frames
within which they set their tasks and through which they bound their
institutional settings. (270)
They (konstanterne)
tend to change over periods of time longer than a single episode
of practice, although particular events may trigger their change.
And they are sometimes changed through the practitioners reflection
on the evens of his practice. (275)
Even if reflection-in-action
is feasible, however, it may seem dangerous. ..It may seem to do
so for four different reasons:
There is no
time to reflect when we are on the firing line; if we stop to think,
we may be dead.’
When we think
about what we are doing, we surface complexity, which interferes
with the smooth flow of action. The complexity that we can manage
unconsiously paralyzes us when we bring it to consciousness.
If we begin
to reflect-in-action, we may trigger an infinite regress of reflection
on action, then on our reflection on action, and so on ad infinitum.
The stance
appropriate to reflection is incompatible with the stance appropriate
to action. (278)
Our question
then is not so much whether to reflect as what kind of reflection
is most likely to help us get unstuck. (280)
That fear that
reflection-in-action will trigger an infinite regress of reflection
derives from an unexamined dichotomy of thought and action. If we
separate thinking from doing, seeing thought only as a preparation
for action and action only as an implementation of thought, then
it is easy to believe that when we step into the separate domain
of thought we will become lost in an infinite regress of thinking
about thinking. But in actual reflection-in-action, as we have seen,
doing and thinking are complementary. Doing extends thinking in
the tests, moves, and probes of experimental action, and reflection
feeds on doing and its results. Each feeds the other, and each sets
boundaries for the other. (280)
A practitioner
might break into a circle of self-limiting reflection by attending
to his role frame, his interpersonal theory-in-use, or the organizational
learning system in which he functions. (283)
Part three:
Conclusions
The traditional
professional-client relationship, linked to the traditional epistemology
of practice, can be described as a contract, a set of norms governing
the behavior of each party to the interaction. (292)
It is important
to note, first of all, that reflective practice does not free us
from the need to worry about the client rights and mechanisms of
professional accountability. My concern is to show how the professional-client
may be transformed, within a framework of accountability, when the
professional is able to function as a reflective practitioner.
Just as reflective
practice takes the form of a reflective conversation with the situation,
so the reflective practitioers relation with his client takes the
form of a literally reflective conversation. (295) (jf. Joharis´
vindue)
Both client
and professional bring to their encounter a body of understandings
which they can only very partially communicate to one another and
much of which they cannot describe to themselves. (297)
Within such
a contract the professional is more directly accountable to his
client than in the traditional contract. There is also room here
for other means of assuring accountability, that is, for peer review,
for monitoring by organized clients, and for the ”default
procedures” of public protest or litigation. (297)
Expert: I am presumed to know,
and must claim to do so, regardless of my own uncertainty.
Reflective
practitioner: I am predumed to know, but I am not the only one in
the situation to have relevant and important knowledge. My uncertainties
may be a source of learning for me and for them.
Expert: Keep
my distance from the client, and hold onto the experts role. Give
the client a sense of my expertise, but convey a feeling of warmth
and sympathy as a ”sweetener”.
RP: Seek out
connections to the client´s thoughts and feelings. Allow his respect
for my knowledge to emerge from his discovery of it in the situation.
Expert: Look
for deference and status in the clients response to my professional
persona.
RF: Look for
the sense of freedom and of real connection to the client, as a
consequence of no longer needing to maintain a professional facede.
(300)
Traditional
contract: I put myself into the professionals hands and, in doing
this, I gain a sense of security based on faith.
Reflective
contract: I join the professional in making sense of my case, and
in doing this I gain a sense of increased involvement and action.
TC: I have
the comfort of being in good hands. I need only comply with his
advise and all will be well.
RC: I can exercise
some control over the situation. I am not wholly dependent on him;
he is also dependent on information and action that only I can undertake.
TC: I am pleased
to be served by the best person availiable.
RC: I am pleased
to be able to test my judgments about his competence. I enjoy the
exitement of discovery about his knowledge, about the phenomena
of his practice, and about myself. (302)
When practitioners
are unaware of their frames for roles or problems, they do not experience
the need to choose among them. They do not attend to the ways in
which they construct the reality in which they function; for them,
it is simply the given reality. (310)
When a practitioner
becomes aware of his frames, he also becomes aware of the possibility
of alternative ways of framing the reality of his practice. (310)
The idea of
an action science has a precursor in the work of Kurt Lewin, much
of which has the thematic character which enables practitioners
to use it in their own reflection-in-action. Such notions as ”gatekeeper
roles”, ”democratic and authoritatian group climates”
and ”unfreezing” are metaphors from which managers,
for examble, can build and test their own on-the-spot theories of
action. (319)
As we try to
understand the nature of reflection-in-action and the process greatly
influenced by ”cognitive emotions”, and by the social
context of inquiry. (322)
Significant
organizational learning – learning which involves significant
change in underlying values and knowledge structure – is always
the subject of an organizational predicament. It is necessary to
effective adaption, but it disrupts the constancies on which manageable
organizational life depends. In addition, as I have notes earilier,
the individual agents of organizational learning operate within
a social system which shapes their behavior. They have individual
interests and theories of action which they bring to the creation
of the behavioral world in which they live, a behavioral world which
may be more or less conducive to the public testing of private assumptions,
the surfacing of dilemmas, and the public discussions of sensitive
issues. They belong to subgroups which often enter into win/lose
games of attack and defense, deception, and collusion. In so far
as these social systems determines the boundaries and directions
of organizational inquiry, they are ”learning systems”;
and in organizations like the consumer products firm they may severely
constrain organizational learning. (328)
Eksempel med skolesystemet s.
329ff
In a school
supportive of reflecting teaching, teachers would challenge the
prevailing knowlegde structure…Conflicts and dilemmas would
surface and move to center stage. In the organizational learning
system with which we are most familiar, conflicts and dilemmas tend
to be suppressed or to result in polarization and political warfare.
(335)
A practitioner
who reflects-in-action tends to question the definition of his task,
the theories-in-action that he brings to it, and the measures of
performanceby which he is controlled. And as he questions these
things, he alsom questions elements of the organizational knowledge
structure in which his functions are embedded. (337)
The existence
of a widespread capacity for reciprocal reflection-in-action is
unlikely to be discovered by an ordinary social science which tends
to detect, and treat as reality, the patterns of institutionalized
contention and limited learning which individuals transcend, if
at all, only on rare occasions. The extent of our capacity for reciprocal
reflection-in-action can be discovered only through an action science
which seeks to make some of us do on rare occasions into a dominant
pattern of practice. (354)
til toppen
|